It's Dark In London, Oscar Zarate, ed., SelfMadeHero, 2012.
A portrait of London that captures the city’s fundamental essence as an
exquisite mixture of lofty towers and gutter sleaze, of suburban
gentility and urban depravity, of private vices and public philanthropy.
"Its Dark in London features the work of Alan Moore, Neil Gaiman, David
McKean, Ilya, Carol Swain, Dix, Melinda Gebbie, in tandem with the stories of
London writers like Iain Sinclair,Graeme Gordon, Christopher Petit and Stella
Duffy. This fusion produces a portrait of London that captures the city's fundamental
essence as an exquisite mixture of lofty towersand gutter sleaze, of suburban
gentility and urban depravity, of private vices and public philanthropy."
“The
mix of illustrators is so good... The book succeeds in making the
reader look at the city with fresh eyes" - TimeOut
"Grim, grimy and fixated by London's underbelly, this clever collection
is an estate agent's nightmare and a psychogeographer's dream. An
impressive list of writers and artists (Alan Moore, Neil Gaiman, Iain
Sinclair) take turns to dig their way into the capital's corners,
uncovering gangsters, musicians, prostitutes, flashers and more than a
few corpses. The pungent sense of the past is partly due to the volume's
history – first published in 1996, it's reissued with a selection of
new prose pieces which veer from the forgettable (Alexei Sayle's tale of
a Crouch End catwoman) to the atmospheric (Sinclair's stroll down
half-gentrified canals). But it's the comic strips that make the book.
Divided by evocative street plans and photos, their techniques pull
against each other in thrilling fashion, from the big, beaming heads
that Carl Flint draws to accompany Chris Webster's "Frozen", to Ilya's
disconcertingly blurred sketches of a perverse autopsy in "The Body".
These tales will linger long after the Olympic fanfare has faded." - James Smart
"If London had been in Argentina,
and only forty years old, with a completely different history,
architecture, population and name – would it still be London? The
madness of the question strikes home quickly. Without England, its
specific history, architecture, population and name, surely there would be no London. London just is what those things (and others) compose. But then are not each of these accidental
features, features that bear only a contingent relationship to London?
Dickens lived in London, but surely it is possible that Dickens may
never have been born. Would then London have ceased? Surely not. London
would survive the failed birth of Dickens. Had Sherlock Holmes been
real, would London have survived this new accidental Fact? Again, it
seems likely that it would. And of each particular detail – including
country, history, architecture, population and name (and others) are
they too not all, in this sense, accidents? And if we can remove each
individual one without removing London, then why not them all? For
surely the fact of all the actual accidental features of London is itself just an accidental feature in the same way as each individual feature is.
This kind of thought raises the
possibility of a metaphysics of London. Perhaps, below the accidental
features of the city, are essences, properties that are necessary and
that contain powers that result in non-accidental manifestations that
would appear no matter the accidental details. These powers
would then be fundamental. There are many truths about London, but the
fundamental powers are truths that would survive even the disappearance
of all accidental features. The forty year old Argentinean city would
then only be London if it had London’s fundamental powers.
How would we understand these
powers? Our intuitions are conditioned by our interactions with
accidental features. Powers are not accidental, and so our intuitions
about how to understand them are likely to be flawed. Philosophers have
thought that perhaps we should stick to what works for purposes of
control. Science has delivered astonishing news about the nature of
nature. So people like Quine suggest we should stick to scientific
methods. Investigating powers should be continuous with the methods of
science. But the purpose and value of science is limited.
Other purposes and values flourish, and these may well be connected
closer to the powers of London than anything dreamt of in the scientific
toolbox.
How can we discover metaphysical London, by which I mean, the fundamental powers of London? You
might say this is crazy. There are no fundamental powers of London. The
contextual relationships that bind the accidental features together
exhaust the definition of London. We can have a successful theory about
London without appeals to metaphysics. London would not survive the
absence of too many of its accidental features. It depends on a
conversational context and our interests. London is subjective. It is
supplied by us. This suggests that London is not fundamental. But this
book suggests a different story. An eerie darkness pervades London, a
dark that seems ever present, a kind of necessary truth. The dark is a
metaphysical truth being disinterred like some strange, ghoulish corpse
bride, Lamia or the teeth of Berenice, and then Berenice.
But what is the role of powers
in metaphysics? They ground objective similarity. What kind of thing
does this? Universals ground objective similarity. What grounds
Universals? Powers. Powers and their manifestations. They ground natural
laws and causes. They ground necessary laws and what is possible.
Zarate calls his collection,
‘It’s Dark In London.’ So we ask: which is the power, which its
manifestation? Manifestation is ambiguous: it can be a process and it
can be a product. And a fundamental ontology may ground either: a
manifestation can be the property of a substance, or it can be a process
relationship. So, is the dark a manifestation of London power, where
London is the power and the dark its manifestation? Or is the dark the
power, and London the manifestation? And when does a substance make its
powers manifest? What stimulation is required to bring out the promised
power. A vase has the power of fragility. Yet it requires a hammer blow
to stimulate that power. A vase can be heated so it melts in the time
between being struck by the hammer and it manifesting its fragility.
That the heat makes it melt instead of shatter shows that the power of
fragility isn’t fundamental. Call such non-fundamental powers
dispositions. We are not seeking dispositions, we are seeking powers.
But if cause and effect are
simultaneous and perhaps identical then there can be no time lag between
cause and effect. The account then preserves a sense of fundamentality.
But this account threatens to be one of mereology, of merely a theory
of part to whole relationships, where the idea of temporal
succession is dropped. And London seems to require time. London
accumulates itself. It’s writers form a procession, though also, it
should be readily admitted, a kind of circularity, where each seems to
borrow their own tongues without remainder. But a timeless notion of
causal power seems to take us off on the wrong track. So a mereological
account assumes the wrong kind of metaphysical backdrop. Metaphysics it
seems can’t be done a bit at a time: it has to fit together with a whole
picture. Metaphysical London requires a notion of time as well as dark.
Alexander Bird says powers are
fundamental dispositions and sparce. Non-fundamental dispositions are
profligate and familiar, like the fragility of a human bone. Fundamental
dispositions are metaphysically necessary. According to Nelson Goodman,
powers carry ‘a threat or promise’ of some manifestation. What
manifestation? The laws of nature themselves, understood as governing
properties (or relations between such properties) in response to some
stimulus. The powers are ultimate. The laws of nature are metaphysically
necessary but explanatorily inert. Only powers have metaphysical
explanatory potency. Their potency seems in inverse proportion to their
rarity.
Subjective conditionals express the powers of dispositional properties. If
the hammer is applied to the bone, the bone will be disposed to smash.
But finks can afflict subjunctive conditionals. If between the impact of
the hammer and the splintering of the bone the bone is melted then the
bone doesn’t smash. Finks can make dispositions inexpressive. Finkish
interference does not afflict powers. A fink is a deeper level of
mechanism than the affected disposition. But powers are the final depth
of explanation. There are no deeper levels. Nothing can alter the
intrinsic state of a power from one moment to the next. There could be
no explanation justifying a detour between stimulation and
manifestation. Therefore powers are resistant to all finks.
Iain Sinclair’s ‘Scarlet Tracings’
investigates the territory of powers not dispositions. His Ripper story
is one that operates with tropes of murders, found letters, lost
addresses, lost places, buried knowledge, secrets and half lit
conjectures that Zarate is calling, as accurate and simple as a
cut-throat, dark. Sinclair is in the place of London power, drafting his
extraordinary psychogeography into a hellish pitch that is a genuine,
forensic maze of blind alleys.
Some scientists puzzle over the
nature of ‘laws of nature’. Some suppose that they are contingent facts.
They think the laws could have been different. We can imagine other
worlds where the manifest properties revealed in response to stimulus
are different from those on our actual world. But then we can ask why we
suppose laws of nature to be more important facts than any other
contingent fact. If Blackstock Road had been the next road down then
would it still have death dancing through the unlit story of Graeme
Gordon and Dix? Why when we suppose we’ve lost everything don’t we
suppose we’ve lost the laws of nature along with everything else? Or the
ability to scream in terror. Or else just silently feel the dread.
Alexander Bird fancies he has the answer. Laws of nature are metaphysically
necessary. They are merely whatever the promises – or threats – of
powers necessarily deliver. As powers, they are necessary and so exist
in all possible worlds. The laws of nature, being necessary
manifestations of these powers, are also what exist in all possible
worlds. Alan Moore stalks Highbury, tracking the oxymoronic traces
through gravediggers’ bootprints high on a hill. He sees disappointment
in Karl Marx’s eyes. Marx’s scientific laws seem weaker than those of
the physicist, even of the moon necromancer. His own counter-legals
recall Marxist anthropologist Semenov proposing a version of dialectic historicism which made it imaginable that, with
tweaks, there would have been no Revolution. How weak, his sad eyes
register, is the necessity of Utopian historicism. Ehrenfest, in another
bar, or library booth, shows that had electric force been a tad
stronger then nuclear force would have been too weak to hold protons
together in a carbon nuclei. Both Marxism and carbon-based life rest
more on luck than any absolute.
Sighing into this fleeting
moment, Moore agrees, sees London as a bedlam where madmen try to
hallucinate the end of carbon with doxies and scandal, and plunges into
further darks. Poets, Samuel Taylor Coleridge in this case, wander down
the Holloway Road wondering that had gravity declined with separation
cubed then planetary orbits would have been unstable. Unsteady with his
chemists’ stew, the poet trembles by the sex shops, antiques emporia and
hot street food with a vision of glassy, dark, vampiric forces in a
dark ice river falling to hell round about the Lea.
The great beast himself,
Aleister Crowley, heroin addict and asthmatic, is in a house of a
Highbury printer, and supposing that even had he managed to alter
electricity and gravity, the various truths of maths and the metaphysics
of space and time, the fundamental dynamical laws linking the forces of
motion and the law governing composition of forces would all remain
unaltered. Moore wanders his beserker mind through this demonological
brood, lightens up with the quack-drug antics of a 1925 Arsenal team
looking for cup glory that ends in spectacular defeat before zooming in
to Dorothy Squires in the Tempo – ‘where the Garage is today’ – she’s
singing badly whilst Roger Moore is Alan’s ungracious double, ‘Ivanhoe
with a chivalric bypass ’ before spirits howl from inside Holloway
Prison and he scuttles away.
Is it all necessary? Or is it
just accidental? Or maybe the themes make a point of standing somewhere
in a grading, from necessary to accidental and everything else in
between. We ask; why does it seem that some laws show more
counterfactual resilience? This is the centre point of the volume. It is
a restless piece of metaphysical fragmentation, climbing out of its
once-rejected backwater, (ditched there by logical positivism and the
linguistic turn for a brief while) and making it back to semi-decency
again. These stories form the sinewy tentacles of the metaphysical
Kraken, the same that ruined Melville after his Leviathan formed first
his lived obscurity. This is writing looking for its afterlife.
Metaphysics rejects the
eighteenth century conviction that all sources of knowledge are
empirical. It reverses the perspective of 19th century positivists who thought that metaphysics was an intermediate stage before science. In
the eighties logical positivist and Tottenham fan AJ Ayer argued with
the youngest heavyweight champion of the world Mike Tyson over some sex
need and it becomes a metaphor: Tyson the metaphysical power confronting
the supposed constraints of the merely seen. Science becomes second order work, merely the investigation and codification of the laws governing the manifestations of stimulated powers. Powers were the explanatory, metaphysical ultimates. Powers were, like Tyson, power.
Metaphysics rejects the
linguistic turn associated with Wittgenstein also, where problems of
metaphysics and philosophy are reduced to linguistic analysis.
Wittgenstein thought metaphysics an illusion caused by systematic
confusion of grammar rules.
Rejecting empiricism and
language philosophers, the metaphysician determines to ask questions
about fundamental truths without apology or embarrassment. But once onto
it, the writers steeped in London lore identify the dark as the essence
power of London, the rare constant, breeding nightmares. Neil Gaiman
locates the once notorious Centre Point building as the spot where Queen
Elizabeth 1st’s Lord mayor caught a fox. It became a rookery
– ‘ a warren of houses jerrybuilt onto houses, lightless courts, alleys
and dead ends; a true warren – you could enter through a door of one
building, leave through a door in another, far away, which made a
rookery the perfect place for people who didn’t want to be arrested.’
This was part of the wildness of London, a metaphysics ruthlessly
denying that everything was as it seemed, that actually the powers were
deeper than the law, deeper than those in New Oxford Street who
complained of the rookery’s stink. ‘ … a hundred and sixty years later,
the streets are cleaner, and the buildings have water and drains’
comments Gaiman, but ‘There are still the hunters, and there is always
the prey.’
The sequence of narratives,
drifts, half-maps and ghost-details raises issues of how we could ever
know this complex maze. It seems the daemon writer, in knowing the
complexity, must be as complex as the universe containing it. And so we
face a book working like a mise en abyme, a Droste
Effect, an image containing its own image containing its own image
seemingly continuing forever (Think the cover of Pink Floyd’s Ummaguna,
Escher’s mapped spiral images and of course the Dutch cocoa powder
image after which the effect is named). Think of a mirror reflecting
another mirror. Each story, each sentence, each picture is such that we
seem to be able to predict all our futures but how can just knowing
things now have such a power? These are more than just stories: they are
what the powers manifest: London dark.
And the secrets within the stories generate a further paradox, a paradox of knowability. A single unknown truth q yields an unknowable truth – that is: q and no-one knows q.
Think of the unknown heinous crime, at the Court, Kensal Rising,
Highbury, Centre Point, Holborn and then everywhere else. Read about it
and then realize the impossibility of all this. That knowing that there
is an unknown heinous crime is itself unknowable.
The book retreats before this
inevitable screw-up, knowing the danger too well to fall for it. So the
narratives come on as fictions, close-by cousins of a world of ‘if-then’
conditionals. A clever conceit. As fiction, it no longer has to be as
complex as its world. But the paradoxes of prediction and unknowability
hover around in the shadows like texts that could have been
always do. Pierre-Simon Laplace reviewed these works back in 1814, his
mind inhabited by a demon with an intellect which at a certain moment
knew all the forces that set nature in motion, and all positions of all
items of which nature is composed, an intellect vast enough to submit
these data to analysis, embracing in a single formula the movements of
the greatest bodies of the universe and those of the tiniest atom; and
so for such an intellect nothing was uncertain and the future was like
the past, present before its eyes…. – and so, at the moment the demon
understood the paradox of complexity, prediction and unknowability, she
came to a terrible self knowledge, shrieking ‘I am merely conditional…’
to disappear into an inky dark self-cancellation. This
demon Borges gave a name to: the Aleph, and in so doing endowed it a
sinister and uncanny tribute.
Powers shimmer their manifestations in lurid dark, cross-fertilized at the sanctum regnum of British legend, Kings Cross. As Aiden Andrew Dun
has it: Blake’s ‘Golden Quatrain holds the key to this: ‘The fields
from Islington to Marybone/to Primrose Hill and Saint John’s Wood/ were
builded over with pillars of gold,/and there Jerusalem’s pillars stood.’ The
metaphysically necessary is gridded out by Blake here: the Old Church
of Saint Pancras is the oldest church in Britain, ‘ The Head and Mother
of all Christian Churches, under Highgate, near London’ whose foundation
stone was, like Glastonbury, laid by a twenty-something Jesus himself
during his ‘lost years’. Attested to by Pan-European medieval
literature, it is out of this that the luminous Aiden Andrew Dun finds
the poems of Rimbaud’s Illuminations filtering a poetic essence through an obscure mystical geography of hills surrounding Kings Cross in his insideous ‘Rimbaud, Psychogeographer.’
So again, the question posed by
this collection is whether the dark of London is an essential power of
London or not. Or vice versa? One direction of questioning continues to
doubt: even if London possesses its dark necessarily, it doesn’t follow
that dark is an essence of London. London is necessarily in the
singleton set containing London, but ‘being in that set’, though
necessary, is not an essence of London.
But what if the dark will always
exist in London from now on, because the dark is something that cannot
end, once acquired? Wouldn’t that make it an essence of London? It for
sure would be something that London can’t exist without. But no, it
wouldn’t follow that dark was London’s essence, even were this true.
Darkness may be a quality that persists and may be something that, once
existing, persists forever. In such a case London, having
acquired the quality of darkness would never be able to exist without
it, because of the supposition that darkness persists forever. But many
such qualities might not have been acquired. If the dark might
not have been acquired then it isn’t a necessary acquisition. It would
be merely an accidental feature that persists forever. So is London’s
dark such an accident? Or is London the dark’s power made manifest?
The treatment of the dark in
this volume, and throughout the range of works developed by these
writers and artists, gives inordinate weight to this accidental fact.
That it is a fact being taken to have such significance suggests that
rather than being an accident is at least more necessary than
merely accidental. The writings suggest not just that the dark will
persist forever, but that it could not have been otherwise. In other
words, perhaps the better way of seeing this dark clearly is to reverse
the cause and effect: darkness persists forever, and one of its
necessary manifestations is London.
So the writings here are
exercises in a metaphysical not an epistemological dark. It’s certainly
no matter of quaint picturesque. In other words, Zarate and his crew – Josh Appignanes, Steve Bell, Dix, Stella Duffy, Jonathan Edwards, Carl Flint, Neil Gaiman, Melinda Gebbie, Graeme Gordon, Tony Grisoni, Chris Hogg, Stewart Home, Ilya, Garry Marshall, Dave McKean, Alan Moore, Chris Petit, Woodrow Phoenix, Warren Pleece, Alexei Sayle, Iain Sinclair,
Yana Stajno, Carol Swan and Chris Webster are not asking about what we
know about dates, times, places, people, events but rather relating
their sources to a modal, non-epistemological form of enquiry. These are
stories about necessity and possibility. All the names, locations,
rumors and narratives are accumulated not in order to clarify names,
locations, rumors, and narratives, but rather as an attempt to know just
what is ultimate.
Jack the Ripper may not be the
person we think he is, and we might work out ways of discovering his
true identity, but that kind of enquiry would be merely epistemological.
Had the actual individual who was Jack the Ripper had parents different
from those he actually had, would he have still been Jack the Ripper?
Was there a dark essence of the Ripper that was essential, necessary
rather than being an accidental feature of circumstance, biology,
culture, hereditary madness or whatever? That’s the modal, metaphysical
investigation repeated here in this volume again and again. Think of the
old joke: ‘You want to know how to get from here to Neasden? Well,
first of all I wouldn’t start from here…’
If metaphysical London dark is a
power, and a power is a necessary disposition, then setting that power
in motion produces laws which may be investigated as scientists might
the analogous necessary laws of nature. They are metaphysically
necessary because they are necessarily produced by necessary
metaphysical powers, but they explain nothing. The power explains. So
these narratives are what the London dark manifests. They
explain nothing but are themselves explained by powers of dark that they
manifest. Zarate and his crew are metaphysical writers seeking out the
threats and promises of London’s necessary power. Both dark and London
are necessary in a strict sense. London dark is the ultimate power
manifested by the narratives of writers who dare show what the necessary
dark promises.
London is therefore rare, for
powers, unlike non-necessary dispositions, are scarce. Literary,
artistic, necromantic, metaphysical stimulation produces necessary
manifestations of darkness, analogous to the laws of nature discovered
by scientists. Psychogeographic urges trance out these metaphysical
rounds. It is no accident that nothing here is surprising. Regularities
can chime true but not all regularities correspond to laws. This is what
again and again these writers test themselves with as they write:
setting out their narratives they then scrutinize what is happening to
ask: ‘but is it a law?’ It’s the test of their truth.
Iain Sinclair has it almost down
to a riff now, a ritual that seems to be on automatic pilot. Gaiman
and Alan Moore are more various, they strain their content wider to see
how far the dark extends: they ask how much counterfactual resilience is
there in their content. Both stray much more into transmutational
stories of magik and divine ordinance, developing cracked hallucinatory
narratives where we are invited to wonder how much their alternative
realms can retain familiar features.
Duns Scotus argued for a
haecceity, a non-qualitative property necessarily possessed by exactly
its possessive individual. So London’s dark may be its haecceity rather
than any qualitative property. It is ‘in’ London as an essence of London
itself, a power, rather than a property manifestation caused by powers.
A curious anomaly in this is
Stewart Home. It occurs to me that perhaps of all these writers his
brutal laughter is the laughter of the Platonist. He writes as if
essences are unlikely. No region is essentially anything. All
truths are truths about the non-temporal/spatial Forms. These never
change. They are knowable. Home’s laughter is the brutal laughter of the
Ancients scorning the medievalist. Medieval metaphysics, especially
their powers metaphysics, sets constraints that Plato and his gang
don’t.
The Truth about London’s dark is
a Form, and as such it would never change and is located nowhere.
Instead of essences and haecceities, Home
asks what things relative to the Form Dark are here, now? Reading Home
you sense that his Platonic Forms are just a belief in all the facts. As
such, he goes all brutal on the modern philosopher king: ‘If there’s
one thing I hate more than an artist it’s a right wing wanker who writes
philosophy books’ snears the character Luther Blisset in ‘Too Late’. In
this story, the Heideggarian councillor shoots himself to prove his
humanity. Karen Elliott murmurs that they arrived too late.
The secret of the story is again
a question of what was necessary. Was the councillor’s death caused by
his own hand? At first glance it seems so. But then consider that had he
not shot himself, Karen Elliot would have bricked him to death.
Explaining causal powers in terms of ‘if he’d not pulled the trigger, he
wouldn’t have died’ won’t work here, because even had he not pulled the
trigger, he would have died. The Heideggerian philosopher dies as a
metaphysical jokee. And it is is a very dark joke indeed.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.